The Communist Manifesto:
Philosophic and Economic Ideas/
Historic Consequences
Karl Marx claimed that
economics determines history, and that one's economic class determines one's
ideas. Ironically, he proved himself wrong, in a deadly way. The
twelve-thousand word propaganda tract written by Marx in 1848 and known as The
Communist Manifesto was a concise summary of many ideas which Marx himself
created. These ideas proceeded to shape the history of the twentieth century,
including its political and economic history, as well as the ideas of most
twentieth century intellectuals. This history included approximately one
hundred million innocent citizens slaughtered by their governments, millions
more enslaved by their governments, international conflicts on an unprecedented
scale, and an intellectual tradition that, at present, is thoroughly entrenched
in the humanities and is in the process of destroying the ideas and ideals of
the West. There have probably never been fewer words that have caused more
misery and destruction than those written by Karl Marx in The Communist
Manifesto.
Contrary to Marx's professed beliefs, ideas have consequences.
The source of the misery and destruction caused by Marx's ideas is the fact
that they are fundamentally false, false philosophically, economically and
historically. In the instance of Marx's ideas, the true causal chain extends
from his false metaphysical, epistemological and ethical premises, to his
politics and economics, to the bloody history of the twentieth century.
The underlying epistemological error that Marx commits early in
the Manifesto is the advocacy of a form of intellectual determinism and
relativism which denies both free will and objectivity by claiming that the
truth and falsehood of one's ideas bear no objective status and are determined
by, and their truth relative to, one's economic class. He says, "Your very
ideas are but the outgrowth of the conditions of your bourgeois production and
bourgeois property… don't wrangle with us so long as you apply… the standard of
your bourgeois notions of freedom, culture, law, etc." And: "Law,
morality and religion are… bourgeois prejudices, behind which lurk in ambush
just as many bourgeois interests."
What Marx is claiming here is that the entire Western
philosophic and intellectual tradition, as it had developed up until his time
(and on which, ironically, he was entirely dependent for his own ideas), is a
subjective rationalization used to justify the "exploitation" of the
workers by the capitalists, a tradition consisting of ideas which are neither
consciously chosen by the capitalists, nor have any basis in fact. Thus, in a
single swoop, Marx himself rationalizes the destruction not only of entire
fields, such as law, but of Western culture as such, including its most
fundamental concepts, such as "freedom." (Contemporary manifestations
of these Marxian premises taught in modern universities include the doctrines
of "Deconstruction," "Neo-Pragmatism," and "Multiculturalism.")
Of course, if the entire body of Western thought is a subjective
rationalization, there can be no such thing as "objectivity," or any
defense, based on such a concept, of the institutions of a civilization founded
upon it. Having dismissed freedom, culture, morality and law as subjective
myths, Marx then feels free to advocate their outright destruction by the
totalitarian State, which he refers to as the "Communistic modes of…
appropriating intellectual products," resulting in the elimination of
"class culture."
Following Marx's theory, within a few months of coming to power,
Vladimir Lenin quickly eliminated the "bourgeois notion" of law in
practice by setting up a secret police, the Cheka, which controlled secret
courts authorized to fix penalties in accordance with "the dictates of the
revolutionary conscience" (i.e. without reference to written law or
objective standards). The random killing of groups of people, linked by class
status or profession (such as homeowners and high school teachers) immediately
followed. The "bourgeois notion" of freedom was eliminated by
throwing those who were not murdered outright into concentration and labor
camps. Consistent with Marxian subjectivism, objections to slave labor were
brushed aside by Lenin's associate Karl Radek as "the bourgeois prejudice
of 'freedom of labor'".
Hitler, of course, would soon apply the same methods on a larger
scale in his "National Socialism," adapting the Soviet model to his
own ideology by substituting the concept of race for class. Thus, in Marx's
epistemological ideas, began the intellectual subjectivism, the moral
relativism, and mass murder of the totalitarian governments in our century.
The "Communistic modes of… appropriating intellectual
products" in order to eliminate "class culture" were made a
reality both in the Soviet Union and Red China, whose leaders, Stalin and Mao,
systematically smashed Western culture in "Cultural Revolutions" in
1946 and 1966-67 respectively. During these intellectual purges,
Western-influenced "bourgeois" scientists and artists were killed or
imprisoned, while their works were destroyed.
Marx's non-objectivity is intricately linked to his policy of
equivocation and conceptual redefinition. If there are no objective standards
of knowledge, there can be no fixed, objective definitions of concepts. In
fact, under the guise of using "dialectic logic," Marx and his
followers usually give key concepts the exact opposite of their exact meaning.
Thus the term "slavery," which in reality is a state maintained by the
slave master by the threat of physical coercion against the slave, is used by
Marx to describe the condition of the workers, who in fact are persuaded to
work by the exact opposite of coercion, that is, by the offering of a positive
reward, i.e. money. (A leading Marxist theorist of early Soviet Russia, Nikolai
Bukharin, described capitalist labor as "the enslavement of the working
class," and Soviet concentration camps as "the self-organization of
the working class.") Similarly, for Marx voluntary trade for mutual gain
represents the "exploitation" of one party by another; whereas
expropriation, i.e. robbery, the forced, unrewarded transfer of wealth from one
party to another, has come, under Marx's influence, to represent social
"justice." By extension of the same technique, twentieth century
Marxists have distinguished between Capitalist "imperialism" (free
trade between independent countries) vs. "wars of liberation"
(Communist-initiatied wars of aggression leading to government
"expropriation" (robbery) of private property and the enslavement of
the population), as well as many other Orwellian slight-of-hands. (Nikita
Krushchev declared in 1961: "The Communist victory will take place
through… 'national liberation wars' in Africa,
Asia and Latin America,
the 'centers of revolutionary struggle against imperialism'.")
The shortest outline of an answer to Marx's epistemological
falsehoods is the following: that both correctly formed concepts and true
propositions made up of such concepts are objective, i.e. correspond to the facts
of an absolute and knowable reality; that people possess free will, i.e. are
able choose to expend the effort to think or not, and therefore the possess the
ability to arrive at truth by an effort which is volitionally exercised; that
the ideas at which people arrive determine their actions (including their
economic actions) and therefore their history; and that the application in
action of true ideas has pro-life consequences, the application of false ideas,
anti-life consequences.
The underlying false ethical assumption which permeates the
Manifesto and underlies Marx's political and economic ideas is that
self-interest is intrinsically evil and corrupt. Marx speaks of the "naked
self-interest," and "egotistical calculation" of the
Bourgeoisie, who, by offering payment in exchange for the services of
physicians, lawyers and poets, "stripped of its halo every occupation
hitherto honored and looked up to with reverent awe."
What, in essence, is implied by such a statement? That because
an instance of trade is advantageous to one or (in fact) both parties, because
it appeals to their "naked self-interest," by that very fact it must
be considered corrupt and evil—that self-interest is corrupt and evil—that the
source of personal honor is self-sacrifice, as opposed to self-preservation. As
identified by Ayn Rand, implicit in such a view is a premise of death as the
ultimate standard of value motivating one's moral actions, actions which, in
order for one to claim a positive moral status, one may never be the beneficiary
of. Here, in what is perhaps the fundamental issue underlying ethics
(self-preservation versus self-sacrifice as the standard of morality), we see
the suggestion of a moral standardùin fact, an inversion of good and evilùthat,
when put into existential practice, will lead to the rationalization of
countless human deaths, to the sacrifice of countless "selfish"
individuals, a wholesale slaughter of human beings on a scale never before seen
or imagined, in the service of "the greater good" of others, of
humanity as a whole.
In Marxist political practice, the selfish, i.e. profit-seeking,
individuals are identified as any professional group (Marx mentions landlords
and shopkeepers) who have amassed more wealth relative to any other
professional group through an act of trade, which other group it is assumed
they have "exploited." Once such a group has been identified, Marx
believes it is morally justified to "expropriate the expropriators"
by an act of force. (Note Marx's establishment of the notion of a collective,
rather than individual, guilt deserving of a collective punishment.)
This standard of morality was applied by Joseph Stalin in
1929-36 to a class of peasants he called the "Kulaks." (Kulak
literally means "fist"; as a descriptive term applied to the peasants
it means "grasping peasant.") To help speed industrialization Stalin
wanted a greater production of food from the peasants, who formed approximately
3/4 of the Russian population. Because most peasants would not accept Stalin's
paper money in trade, he sent armed government officials to seize the peasant's
produce by force. Those peasants who resisted being robbed of either their land
or their production were labeled "Kulaks" and were said to be
engaging in "terrorist acts." To stop these "terrorist
acts," Stalin called for an "all-out offensive against the Kulak…We
must smash the Kulaks, eliminate them as a class…We must strike at the Kulaks
so hard as to prevent them from rising to their feet again…We must break down
the resistance of that class in open battle!"
The result of the ensuing war-like operation of the government
against its citizens was an estimated 10 million men, women & children
gunned down, and 10-11 million more transported to North European Russia, Siberia and Central Asia
where a third went into concentration camps, a third into internal exile, and a
third were executed or died in transit. The remaining peasants, who were
stripped of their property and herded into "grain factories,"
revolted by destroying equipment and produce. Stalin's offensive against the
peasents thus caused what was to be "perhaps the only case in history of a
purely man-made famine."
It must be emphasized that the "terror famine" was not
a misapplication of Marxism, but the implementation of one of The Communist
Manifesto's explicit goals: the "establishment of industrial armies,
especially for agriculture." In a division of labor, when self-interested
trade is condemned as immoral in a government's ideology, political means, i.e.
government force, is all that remains to motivate people to produce. In Ayn
Rand's eloquent words, the alternative to the dollar is the gun.
On an economic level, Marx sees the self-interested acts of
producers and traders as resulting in the steadily increasing impoverishment of
the many, the proletariat, to the benefit of the few, the bourgeoisie. On this
and many related economic points, Marx contradicts not only economic theory as
it had developed by his time, but his own account of recent history, as well as
elementary logic.
For example, he writes, "The bourgeoisie, during its rule
of scant one hundred years, has created more massive and more colossal
productive forces than have all proceeding generations together," and then
later, that "the average price of wage labor is the minimum wage… required
to keep the laborer in bare existence as a laborer," and , "the
modern laborer… instead of rising with the progress of industry, sinks deeper
and deeper below the conditions of existence of his own class," and finally,
that the bourgeoisie is unfit to "rule," because "it is
incompetent to insure an existence to its slave [i.e., the Capitalist's
employees] within his slavery [i.e., the employee is eventually reduced to
literal starvation]." In other words, the result of a radical increase in
the production of goods is the radical impoverishment, even ultimately the
literal starvation, of the vast majority of humanity, the proletariat.
The first logical question to ask following such a fantastic
progression of assertions is that, if the workers are dying of starvation, who
exactly then are the buyers of the Capitalist's goods? Does the Capitalist
produce goods which he subsequently buries in landfills? In logic, a radical
increase in the production of goods is synonymous with a radical increase in
prosperity, an inference demonstrated by the continuous and progressive
increase in the prosperity of both the workers and the employers of the
predominantly Capitalistic countries of the West during the past two centuries.
In economic terms, the equation of wages (i.e. money) with
wealth implied by Marx's quote is based on a Mercantilist fallacy dispelled by
the Classical economists, whose ideas Marx was intimately familiar with at the
time he wrote the Manifesto. In short, one of the central points these thinkers
taught was that real wealth consists not in quantity of the medium used as a
means of exchange, i.e. paper or gold, but rather in the actual goods one can
buy with these mediums, which they called "real wages." If production
is increased, the goods which one can buy with one's salary is increased, and
in turn so is one's prosperity. Given this perspective it becomes irrelevant
whether the worker's salaries average one dollar an hour or one hundred dollars
an hour; what matters is what the salary can buy, and as production increases,
so do the actual goods the average worker can afford.
A Marxist might contend that during Marx's time the goods
manufactured were priced at a high level which only the capitalists could
afford. Such an assertion would be factually wrong, however; describing the
results of the same Industrial Revolution in which Marx perceived increasing
poverty leading to starvation, Jacob Bronowski writes:
"The new inventions were
for everyday use. The canals were arteries of communication: they were not made
to carry pleasure boats, but barges. And the barges were not made to carry
luxuries, but pots and pans and bales of cloth, boxes of ribbon, and all the
common things that people buy by the pennyworth." "It is comic to think
that cotton underwear and soap could work a transformation in the lives of the
poor. Yet these simple things—coal in an iron range, glass in the windows, a
choice of food—were a wonderful rise in the standard of life and health…"
Of course, that standard has kept rising, in the Capitalist and
semi-Capitalist countries, through the present, with it's previously
undreamed-of standard of living for everyone, including of course the working
class.
In another example of historic, political, economic, and logical
self-contradiction, Marx writes that, "National differences and
antagonisms between peoples are daily more and more vanishing, owing to…
freedom of commerce…" Then, writing of end of "exploitation" to
be brought about by the introduction of Communism, Marx writes that, "In
proportion as the antagonism between classes within the nation vanishes, the
hostility between one nation to another will come to an end." Again, in
logic, one is led to ask: if freedom of commerce leads to harmony among
nations, why would the opposite policy, the abolition of freedom of commerce,
now solve the already solved, now nonexistent problem of international
antagonisms, rather than, logically, lead to the opposite result? To understand
why economic freedom historically led to harmony among nations, and what effect
the abolition of economic freedom would cause (and, in fact, later did cause)
among nations, however, requires an analysis which Marx wisely avoids in the
Manifesto.
There is, in fact, both a political and an economic explanation
for the harmony among nations engendered by free enterprise and acknowledged by
Marx. The political explanation is that, under Capitalism, both in regard to
the interactions among private individuals and between private individuals and
the government, the initiation of physical force is legally prohibited, which
principle establishes that both individual people and individual nations, in
seeking their individual ends, must deal with one another through strictly
voluntary means. The economic principle which follows from this is that of free
trade, any instance of which only takes place when both parties deem it to
serve their individual self interest, i.e. when a mutual gain results. Under
such a system, physical aggression is in principle abolished on a political
level, and individual people and individual nations become economic allies who
benefit from each other's existence—i.e., a harmony among people and among
nations results.
Marx, of course, regards cooperation among voluntary traders, when
some of the traders in question are Capitalists trading money for labor, as
"exploitation." How then, according to Marx, is such
"exploitation" to be ended? As in most of Marx's positive assertions,
the means to what he treats as a self-evidently noble end is left unidentified.
(It is probably this technique of deliberately omitting from discussion the
necessary means of implementing his ideas that underlies the common view that
Marxism is a noble theory that has been misapplied in practice by corrupt leaders.)
In reality, however, the only way for a government to prohibit one producer of
goods or services from trading with other producers is through the initiation
(or the threat of the initiation) of physical force against the traders, a
force which aims to rob a producer of his production in order to redistribute
it to a non-producer, under the Marxist policy of "from each according to
his ability to each according to his need." Such a policy, justified by
the antecedent moral principle that seeking one's self-interest is inherently
evil, establishes the principle that the initiation of physical force is a
proper function of government in order to coerce naturally immoral,
self-interested individuals into pursing moral, altruistic ends. It follows in the
economic realm that individual people can no longer be allies, but must become
antagonists, since the gain in property of one person must now represent the
forcible loss of property of another. Politically, it logically must also
follow that if the initiation of force by the government against Capitalistic
"exploiters" is a proper policy on a national level, it must also be
so on an international level.
This, in fact, is the root the Russian enslavement of Eastern Europe, of the "cold war" between the Soviet Union and the United States, and of the many
Communist sponsored third world "revolutions" which took place from
the 1970s onward. Regarding the latter, historian Paul Johnson, in recalls
that: "in December 1975, under Soviet naval escort, the first Cuban troops
landed in Angola.
In 1976 they moved into Abyssinia, now in the Soviet camp, and into Central and
East Africa…by the end of the 1970s there were ten such African states,
providing Soviet Russia, in varying degrees, with diplomatic and propaganda
support, economic advantages and military bases."
In summary, ideas determine history, not the
other way around. True ideas have pro-life consequences, false ideas have
anti-life consequences. Marxism, as presented in the Communist Manifesto, is
not a noble theory that was misapplied in practice, but a vicious theory that,
when applied, led to unparalleled human disaster. It is therefore imperative to
human well being that the "humanitarians" in our humanities
departments replace all vestiges of Marxist philosophy with philosophically
true ideas and begin teaching them, so that philosophy can lead us to a second
Renaissance, rather than the new dark ages which is the end of the Marxist
road. Those ideas are, above all, the ideas of Aristotle, John Locke and Ayn
Rand.
No comments:
Post a Comment